Lesson 4:
The Origin of Knowledge
|
4.7
The Test for Credibility
A recent survey of school children reveals that many of them are
skeptical about the veracity of information they find on the web
(especially when the source gets the sports scores wrong). Presumably
most adults have similar feelings. There is so much information out
there. What are we to believe?
First, there is common sense. Releases for the Institute for Defense of
Greenery, funded by a company building golf courses, may not be an
entirely unbiased source for environmental information, for example.
Likewise, comments emanating from the Fan Club of Bishop Ussher (who put
the Earth's age at about 6000 years ago) might be treated with a lot
more skepticism than, say, statements by the U.S. Geologic Survey or the
Smithsonian.
However, as we have seen in the case of Percival Lowell (professor of
astronomy at MIT), trustworthiness is not invariably tied to position of
authority. So, one would like a kind of "instant test", a kind of
warning device that indicates the likelihood that garbage is coming our
way.
Unfortunately, there is no such test. However, we are not entirely
helpless in the face of the oncoming stream of (mis-)information. A
checklist might look as follows:
|
Is the statement such that - in principle - it could be proven wrong.
If not, it is not about science. Forget it.
|
Is the statement to the advantage of the one making it. This could be
in regard to money, status, or cultural comfort. If yes: red flag goes up.
|
Is the statement one reflecting wishful thinking. (Wouldn't it be nice
if ...) If yes: suspect junk science.
|
Are there a lot of scientists smiling or yawning when you tell them
about it. If yes: suspect crank science.
|
Are scientists heatedly disagreeing about it. If yes: stay out of it.
Problem under discussion. Wear hard hat.
|
Is the statement made by one who claims he absolutely knows the answer. If yes,
it may be right or wrong, but the declarer is not a scientist for sure.
|
A scientist can never be absolutely sure about anything, because a new
observation or insight might force him to abandon previously cherished
ideas. Every scientific theory implies that something must not happen.
If it does happen, that theory is dead or must be modified. If, for
example, a couple of scientists build a machine which delivers heat
without any input of mass or energy, then our ideas about the
conservation of mass and energy would have to be revised. Scientists are
extremely confident that no such machine will ever be built. If it
should be built, we would decide that there is something that is present
in space and time, cryptically, that can emerge as energy or mass. We
would give it a name, and proceed from there.
When testing hypotheses (such as about the typical life span of stars,
say) scientists use mathematics. They make a large number of observations
(how often do we see stars explode in galaxies) and compare this with
expectations (given the number of stars in the galaxies, how many should
be exploding every year). Such comparisons are a matter of "statistics".
There are in fact two kinds of different statistics: descriptive
statistics, and statistical tests. The first is useful in describing
populations: on average there are so many stars per galaxy, with x
percent having a factor of two less, and y percent having a factor of
two more (x and y tend to be similar). The second explores the
probability that a statement is correct (or false). Take the statement:
"More than half of the stars are double or triple stars." Correct or
false? You need to count the proportion of singles in a sample. Then you
need to establish whether a count of, say, 48% singles establishes the
truth of the statement, given that you only have evidence for a sample
and not the entire population. The answer depends on the sample size. If
you have a large enough sample, you can be pretty sure the statement is
correct. The confidence in the statement is reflected by the likelihood
to be wrong. P < 0.01 means that chances are less than one in a hundred
that the statement is wrong. Most scientists will accept this as a
"true" statement.
|