Lesson 4:
The Origin of Knowledge
|
4.0
Introduction and Overview
We (and all other organisms) are born into a universe that we already
"know" on some level, even without having had any individual experience
at all. It's in our genes. The genes contain detailed instructions for
building a sensory apparatus that is precisely tuned to the signals
which an organism needs to receive and process in order to function
properly, that is, to survive, to grow, and to reproduce.
Concerning our own senses, we have eyes to see the electromagnetic
radiation emitted by the sun (called "light") and reflected off objects.
We have ears to hear vibrations transmitted through the air (called
sound). We have a sense of smell that can make an instantaneous analysis
of molecules dissolved in air or water, and which is highly sensitive
toward certain compounds (hydrogen sulfide being one that can be
detected at extremely low levels). Our eyes cannot see ultraviolet,
although the eyes of many insects can. Our ears cannot hear extremely
high-pitched notes, although the ears of bats can. Our nose is no match
for that of a dog. And we have no sense for telling north from magnetism
(as some birds have) or for disturbance of the electric field around us
(as eels and rays do).
Thus, what we think of as the "real" world around us is actually a
rather specialized representation of this world, which is produced by
the senses we happen to have and rely on. If we could sense infrared
(like pit vipers) our world would be different (as so strikingly
illustrated in the movie "Predator" which featured an alien from outer
space hunting people using their body heat as a signal). We say "I see"
when we understand, because our models of the world around us depend on
our sense of sight. Nothing has expanded our understanding of the world
more than using microscopes to look at the invisibly small, and
telescopes to look at the barely visible and the invisible at great
distance.
So, we build our models of the world around us based on sight. Most of
us see three colors in addition to shades of gray, and our brain puts
together a rich palette of intermediate colors of every hue. We believe
this is what the world is like, because that is what it "looks" like. In
reality, it is our interaction with the world, our response to the
stimulus of signals form it, that we use to build our "world model".
Because our experiences differ, every person on this planet has a
different world model, a kind of "private universe."
In addition to the information received through our senses there is
tradition, that is, the things other people (to begin with, our parents
and teachers) tell us about the world. Most of what we know (or think we
know) about the world around us was told to us by others. The set of
beliefs passed on from one generation to the next makes up "culture".
Being human means being part of a culture. The only thing you really
know is what you believe.
Science is not about listing things that are true, but about finding
ways to discover things that might be true, and ways to prove that
things claimed to be true actually are not. Three types of feats are
counted as success in the making and breaking of hypotheses. One, to
present a hypothesis which can be falsified in principle, but survives
all attempts to kill it. Two, to destroy an hypothesis which has been
generally accepted as valid, because it has stood up a long time. Three,
to find evidence to strengthen and refine some very uncertain
hypothesis. All three feats, of course, will produce more notice if the
hypothesis in question is important than if it does not matter very
much.
Science is about making our universes less private and more generally
accepted, even across cultures. This very same goal is pursued by
tradition, within each culture, which fosters general belief systems.
Thus, when science defends its world view, invoking observation, it
comes up against older claims of world knowledge. These older claims
have deep historical roots. What makes the scientific method
exasperating is that it disregards any claim based on tradition (at
least in principle) and demands that each claim be subject to challenge.
It is a kind of Freedom-of-Information act, translated into the realm of
general knowledge and claims to knowledge. Most of the challenges, in
fact, are not between scientists and nonscientists, but are within
science itself. Science is not so much a body of knowledge as it is an
ongoing discussion on what is acceptable (for now) and what is not.
|